Proponents of different flavors of the
Dutch book argument agree about several things.
First, they agree that the Dutch book
argument relies on the thought that a rational individual will use
graduated credal states to maximize expected utility. Any bets that,
evaluated with respect to the graduated credal state, one expects to
make one better will be taken. For instance, if you have assign a .5
probability that it will rain, the assumption is that you should be
willing to buy a ticket for up to 1 util that pays 2 utils if it
rains and nothing if it doesn't.
Second, the Dutch book argument relies
on the Dutch book theorem. According to this theorem, for any
graduated credal state that fails to conform to the axioms of
probability, there will exist a set of bets each of which has a
positive expected utility (as evaluated by that graduated credal
state) but which collectively guarantees a loss.
The Dutch book argument connects the
failure of a graduated credal state to conform to the axioms of
probability with a certain kind of practical failing. If one has
graduated credal states that don't conform to the axioms, and one
aims to maximize one's expected utility, one can get into foreseeable
trouble.
Since the focus of Dutch book argument
is on the practical upshot of accepting graduated credal states that
violate the axioms of probability, the Dutch book argument is
sometimes criticized on the grounds that it is too reliant on
practical considerations. Aren't the norms of probability a matter of
epistemic, rather than practical rationality? But proponents of the
argument seldom (if ever) claim that the reason why we should follow
the norms is in order to avoid being Dutch-book-susceptible.
One popular strategy for defending the
Dutch book argument from the charge of practicality suggests that
Dutch book theorem shows that graduated credal states that don't obey
the axioms can lead us to value the same set of tickets at different
prices, depending on how they are offered. Value shouldn't be
presentation-sensitive (at least in this way). Therefore, the
graduated credal states themselves are inferred to be somehow
inconsistent.
The thought that the inconsistency of
valuation implies some kind of inconsistency in the graduated credal
states themselves is tempting, but hard to make precise. Instead, I
propose that we think of the Dutch book argument in a Bayesian
fashion. Let a “Bayesian argument” be an argument that proceeds
as follows.
P1 Pr(P | Q) >> Pr(P)
P2 Q
C P
Bayesian arguments are of course
non-deductive, and ultimately the plausibility of the conclusion
depends on the prior probability of P. But when the first premise
holds in a given context, the conclusion in some sense is confirmed
by the second premise.
So, here is how I propose that we
understand Dutch Book arguments:
P1 Intuitively, it is more likely that
graduated credal states must obey rule X (P) if violating rule X
leads to Dutch-book susceptibility(Q), for any rule X.
P2 Violating the axioms of probability
leads us to Dutch-Book susceptibility.
C Graduated credal states must obey
the axioms of probability.
The Dutch book argument can be a good
argument without the conclusion following deductively from the
premises. So long as our prior probabilities make P1 true, P2 should
count as evidence for C. There needn't be any particular reason why
our prior probabilities make P1 true. They may simply be reasonable
priors to have.
It is extremely plausible that P1 is
true. A priori, I wouldn't expect that the correct rules of judgment
would allow for Dutch-book susceptibility. Since conformity to the
axioms does preclude Dutch-book susceptibility, it receives some
support from that result. This argument doesn't get us any closer to
explaining why graduated credal states ought to conform to the axioms
of probability. But it does suggest that they ought to.
No comments:
Post a Comment