Moral nondescriptivism holds that moral claims and moral
judgments don’t, qua moral judgments, undertake any particular descriptive
commitments. My intention here is to offer a lightweight version of nondescriptivism
by offering two theses that I think collectively entail nondescriptivism, but
neither of which involves hefty psychological assumptions.
These two theses are descriptive
insufficiency and functional
conceptualization.
According to descriptive
insufficiency, moral words or concepts fail to have descriptive content
because they do not meet whatever the requirements are for having any
particular content. It is extremely plausible that linguistic or conceptual
content depends to some extent on the use of the word or concept. Other things
(such as naturalness) may play a role, but a word or concept cannot have a
determinate meaning without having a fairly stable or united use. Meaning is an
achievement for a sound or mental token, and not free. Hence it should be
possible for a word or concept to fail to have the kind of use necessary for
having some meaning without being totally unlike the words or concepts that do
have meanings.
Nondescriptivism only requires that moral contents, and the
words or concepts that they are built out of, lack that kinds of uses that are
sufficient for descriptive content.
One very plausible route to descriptive inconsistency is
through an externalist semantics. It is plausible that the meanings of at least
some of our words or concepts depend upon the meaning attributed to them from
the community that we live in. What I mean by the words I use is determined in
part by an intention to use those words in the community-standard way. What happens if there is no
community-standard way to use a given word? Plausibly, the word will then lack descriptive
content. If I intend to mean the same thing by ‘right’ as everyone else, and
there is no fixed descriptive content that everyone else collectively can be
plausibly interpreted as using, then my word lacks descriptive content.
According to
functional conceptualization, what it takes for a judgment to fall under
the concept of a moral judgment is
for it to have a certain functional role (which doesn’t by itself guarantee any
particular representational content). That is, we characterize moral judgments
by their motivational rather than their descriptive role.
There is nothing special about thinking that we might define
a concept in this way. It needn’t imply anything too substantive about the
essential nature of any mental state that falls under it. We could also formulate the concept of a
judgment formed-on-a-Tuesday that applied to all judgments formed on Tuesdays. Or
the concept judgment-that-makes-me-think-about-France that applied to all
judgments that made me think about France.
Neither of these concepts would cut psychology at its joints, but nondescriptivism
needn’t undertake any commitment to do so.
Nondescriptivism could simply state that our concept of a
moral judgment collects together judgments that share a certain feature regardless
of whether that feature forms part of the judgments psychological essence. The
particular relevant features include the relevance (direct or indirect) to
motivation. To make a moral judgment is to make some judgment or other that
plays the moral-judgment-role. Moral judgments qua moral judgments have no
descriptive content.
This thought makes good sense of the fact that motivation
plays an important part in how we think about the judgments of foreign
cultures. Why think that the Romans generally thought about right and wrong? It
can’t be because we see that they made the same decisions we do, because they
often didn’t. Plausibly, it is because they reacted to their judgments in the
same fashion as we do.
These two theses are independently plausible and come
together to form a natural kind of nondescriptivism. The difference between
ordinary descriptive beliefs and moral judgments is twofold. First, moral
judgments are distinguished by their role, rather than their content (though
they may also have content) and second, moral judgments need not have, and
probably often lack, any particular descriptive content.
One nice thing about this lightweight form of nondesriptivism
is that it needn’t imply that actual moral judgments lack descriptive contents.
It may be that they do, or it may be that they don’t. Different cultures might
employ concepts that have different descriptive contents but collectively count
as the same moral concepts by virtue of their role. Or it may be that some
people in our society have moral concepts with certain descriptive contents and
other people have moral concepts with distinct descriptive contents, or no
contents at all.
This might help explain why some people insist that noncognitivism
is absurd because it tells them what they mean with their own concepts. If
content externalism is true, it shouldn’t be obvious what we mean. But even so,
we can agree that realists do have beliefs with genuine descriptive contents,
but as a whole there is no particular descriptive content shared by everyone
who makes moral judgments. (And, unlike hybrid versions of noncognitivism, we
don’t need to hold that every moral judgment has some descriptive content or
other.)
No comments:
Post a Comment